Rationality

Added 23 March 2018: See also my summary and notes here on Stuart Sutherland's "Irrationality" for an introduction to similar content.

This is a summary of Rationality: From AI to Zombies, which is a book-form compilation of Eliezer Yudkowsky's Less Wrong Sequences of 2006-2009. LessWrong.com is a "community blog devoted to refining the art of human rationality."

The PDF version can be found at this link. The HTML version is below the line.




Rationality: Abridged


The writings of
Eliezer Yudkowsky

Summarized by
Quaerendo

Preface

THE PURPOSE OF this book is to summarize Eliezer Yudkowksy’s Sequences in order to provide a shorter and more accessible introduction to the foundational ideas of the rationality community, and to serve as a common reference point. The original Sequences were the result of two years of daily blog posts on OvercomingBias.com (founded by his co-blogger economist Robin Hanson) and later LessWrong.com from 2006 to 2009, dealing with the topics of rational belief and decision-making and the underlying sciences, mathematics and philosophy. In 2015, an edited and reorganized version of the sequences was published as “Rationality: From AI to Zombies”, which consists of six books worth of essays, plus introductions by the editor, Rob Bensinger.

It is a must-read for those who want to improve their thinking and fulfill their goals. RAZ serves both as an introduction to thinking about thinking, and a resource for people interested in digging deeper into epistemology, metacognition, and how to be less wrong. It discusses the math of probability theory and decision theory, and the science of cognitive and social psychology and behavioral economics, which have exposed dozens of systematic flaws in human reasoning. It is one of the best places to start for people who are new to Less Wrong.

Eliezer Yudkowsky works as a decision theorist and researcher at the Machine Intelligence Research Institute (MIRI), a nonprofit with the mission of ensuring that smarter-than-human artificial intelligence has a positive impact. The findings of cognitive science and ideas of naturalistic philosophy explained in RAZ help to motivate why MIRI’s research program exists. In addition to co-founding MIRI and Less Wrong, Yudkowsky has also written the fanfic “Harry Potter and the Methods of Rationality”, which is often cited as the most popular work of Harry Potter fanfiction.

Yudkowsky was moved to write these essays by his professional challenges in AI theory and his own philosophical mistakes, but he has also inspired a wider community of intellectuals and lifehackers on Less Wrong, which in turn helped seed the effective altruism movement (an effort to identify the most high-impact humanitarian charities and causes) as well as the establishment of the Center for Applied Rationality (CFAR), a nonprofit organization that aims to translate the science of rationality into useful techniques for self-improvement.

With the benefit of hindsight, Yudkowsky would have prioritized writing about how to practice the skills without knowing the theory, and how people can do better in their everyday lives; he would have focused more on rational action, not just rational belief; he would have better organized the content; and he would have written more courteously. Not doing these was a mistake. Nevertheless, he still believes his two years of blog posting was better than nothing, and that glimpsing the rhythm of this valuable way of thinking has helped a surprising number of people a surprising amount.

I hope that this summary can extend the reach of the Sequences even further. A summary was needed because the original series of essays was way too long for some people, especially for newcomers to the rationality community who wanted an overview of the core propositions but didn’t have a lot of time available. Furthermore, the existing summaries out there tend to be too short for the unacquainted to fully comprehend the ideas or place them in proper context. Therefore what makes this summary different, is that it is not overly short, and may even be redundant at times (deliberately so, because explaining one point from different angles can help different people understand it better). Of course, it can be useful not just for newcomers but also for older members of the community, to refresh their memories and identify points of departure.

In that spirit, this summary includes all 333 blog posts from RAZ in addition to the supplemental interludes and introductions by Rob Bensinger that are often left out of other summaries. It also sometimes links to other essays that did not make it into RAZ, as a way of providing additional background. Pictures and illustrations have also been reproduced here. At the end, a partial glossary is appended. By clicking the headline of a section (green links), you can read the full article on Less Wrong to dive in deeper, and to read or leave comments.

Each one of the 26 Sequences is summarized across two or three pages on average. While the result is something like a short book in itself, it is still significantly shorter than the 1,750 pages of Rationality: From AI to Zombies. Hence the title: “Rationality: Abridged”.

Finally, and needless to say, the ideas contained herein are not my own, so I don’t take credit for them.

Michael (alias Quaerendo)
January, 2018


Note: Since this page would otherwise have been too long, I have divided it up into six separate entries. 

Contents


Preface. 1
Contents. 3

Part I: Map and Territory. 5
  Predictably Wrong. 6
  Fake Beliefs. 9
  Noticing Confusion. 12
  Mysterious Answers. 15
Interlude: The Simple Truth. 19

Part II: How to Actually Change Your Mind. 20
  Overly Convenient Excuses. 22
  Politics and Rationality. 25
  Against Rationalization. 28
  Against Doublethink. 32
  Seeing with Fresh Eyes. 34
  Death Spirals. 37
  Letting Go. 43

Interlude: The Power of Intelligence. 46
Part III: The Machine in the Ghost 47
  The Simple Math of Evolution. 48
  Fragile Purposes. 51
  A Human’s Guide to Words. 55
Interlude: An Intuitive Explanation of Bayes’s Theorem.. 63

Part IV: Mere Reality. 67
  Lawful Truth. 68
  Reductionism 101. 71
  Joy in the Merely Real 75
  Physicalism 201. 78
  Quantum Physics and Many Worlds. 82
  Science and Rationality. 87
Interlude: A Technical Explanation of Technical Explanation. 91

Part V: Mere Goodness. 94
  Fake Preferences. 95
  Value Theory. 98
  Quantified Humanism.. 104
Interlude: The Twelve Virtues of Rationality. 108

Part VI: Becoming Stronger. 109
  Yudkowsky’s Coming of Age. 110
  Challenging the Difficult 113
  The Craft and the Community

Glossary

Here are some brief explanations of terms used in this summary, adapted from this web page.

§  a priori. A proposition that is reasonable to believe even without any experiential evidence. A priori claims are in some way introspectively self-evident, or justifiable using only abstract reasoning. Pure mathematics is often claimed to be a priori, while scientific knowledge is claimed to be a posteriori, or dependent on (sensory) experience. These two terms shouldn’t be confused with prior and posterior probabilities.
§  affective death spiral. A halo effect that perpetuates and exacerbates itself over time.
§  AI-Box Experiment. A demonstration by Yudkowsky that people tend to overestimate how hard it is to manipulate human beings, and therefore underestimate the dangers of building an Unfriendly AI that can only interact with its environment through verbal communication. One participant plays the role of an AI, while another plays a human whose job it is to interact with the AI without voluntarily releasing it from its “box”. Yudkowsky and a few other people who have role-played the AI have succeeded in getting the human supervisor to agree to release them, which suggests that a superhuman intelligence would have an even easier time escaping.
§  algorithm. A specific procedure for computing some function. A mathematical object consisting of a finite, well-defined sequence of steps that concludes with some output determined by its initial input. Multiple physical systems can simultaneously instantiate the same algorithm.
§  amplitude. A quantity in a configuration space, represented by a complex number. Amplitudes are physical, not abstract or formal. The complex number’s modulus squared (i.e. its absolute value multiplied by itself) yields the Born probabilities, but we don’t know why.
§  anchoring. The cognitive bias of relying excessively on initial information after receiving relevant new information.
§  anthropomorphism. The tendency to assign human qualities to non-human phenomena or objects.
§  beisutsukai. Japanese for "Bayes user." A fictional order of high-level rationalists, also known as the Bayesian Conspiracy.
§  bias. (a) A cognitive bias. In Rationality: From AI to Zombies, this is the default meaning. (b) A statistical bias. (c) An inductive bias. (d) Colloquially: prejudice or unfairness.
§  black box. Any process whose inner workings are mysterious or poorly understood.
§  bucket. See “pebble and bucket.”
§  comparative advantage. An ability to produce something at a lower cost than someone else could. This is not the same as having an absolute advantage; you may be a better cook in general than someone, but that person will still have a comparative advantage over you at cooking some specific dishes. Your cooking skills make your time more valuable. The worse cook may have a comparative advantage at baking bread, for example, since it doesn’t cost them much to spend a lot of time on baking, whereas you could be spending that time creating a large number of high-quality dishes. Baking bread is more costly for the good cook than for the bad cook because the good cook is paying a larger opportunity cost (by giving up more valuable opportunities to be doing other things).
§  conjunction. A compound sentence asserting two or more distinct things, such as "A and B" or "A even though B." The conjunction fallacy is the tendency to count some conjunctions as more probable than their components even though they can’t be more probable (and are almost always less probable).
§  decision theory. (a) The mathematical study of correct decision-making in general, abstracted from an agent's particular beliefs, goals, or capabilities. (b) A well-defined general-purpose procedure for arriving at decisions, e.g. causal decision theory.
§  entanglement. (a) Causal correlation between two things. (b) In quantum physics, the mutual dependence of two particles' states upon one another. Entanglement in this sense occurs when a quantum amplitude distribution cannot be factorized.
§  entropy. (a) In thermodynamics, the number of different ways a physical state may be produced (its Boltzmann entropy). For example, a slightly shuffled card deck has lower entropy than a fully shuffled one, because there are many more configurations a fully shuffled deck is likely to end up in. (b) In information theory, the expected value of the information contained in a message (its Shannon entropy). A random variable’s Shannon entropy is how many bits of information one would be missing (on average) if one did not know the variable’s value. Boltzmann entropy and Shannon entropy have turned out to be equivalent: a system’s thermodynamic disorder corresponds to the number of bits needed to fully characterize it.
§  epistemic. Concerning knowledge.
§  eutopia. Yudkowsky’s term for a utopia that’s actually nice to live in, as opposed to one that’s unpleasant or infeasible.
§  evolution. (a) In biology, change in a population’s heritable features. (b) In other fields, change of any sort.
§  expected utility. A measure of how much an agent’s goals will tend to be satisfied by some decision, given uncertainty about the decision’s outcome. Accepting a 5% chance of winning a million dollars will usually leave you poorer than accepting a 100% chance of winning one dollar, because nine times out of ten, the certain one-dollar gamble has higher actual utility. Nevertheless, we say that the 10% shot at a million dollars is better because it has higher expected utility in all cases.
§  fitness. See “inclusive fitness.”
§  formalism. A specific way of logically or mathematically representing something.
§  function. A relation between inputs and outputs such that every input has exactly one output. A mapping between two sets in which every element in the first set is assigned a single specific element from the second.
§  graph. In graph theory, a mathematical object consisting of simple atomic objects (vertices, or nodes) connected by lines (edges) or arrows (arcs).
§  happy death spiral. See “affective death spiral.”
§  hedonic. Concerning pleasure.
§  heuristic. An imperfect method for achieving some goal. A useful approximation. Cognitive heuristics are innate, humanly universal brain heuristics.
§  inclusive fitness. The degree to which a gene causes more copies of itself to exist in the next generation. Inclusive fitness is the property propagated by natural selection. Unlike individual fitness, which is a specific organism’s tendency to promote more copies of its genes, inclusive fitness is held by the genes themselves. Inclusive fitness can sometimes be increased at the expense of the individual organism’s overall fitness.
§  instrumental value. A goal that is only pursued in order to further some other goal.
§  Machine Intelligence Research Institute. A small non-profit organization that works on mathematical research related to Friendly AI. Yudkowsky co-founded MIRI in 2000, and is the senior researcher there.
§  magisterium. Stephen J. Gould’s term for a domain where some community or field has authority. Gould claimed that science and religion were separate and non-overlapping magisteria, meaning that religion has authority to answer questions of “ultimate meaning and moral value” (but not empirical fact) and science has authority to answer questions of empirical fact (but not meaning or value).
§  map and territory. A metaphor for the relationship between beliefs (or other mental states) and the real-world things they purportedly refer to.
§  Maxwell’s equations. In classical physics, a set of differential equations that model the behavior of electromagnetic fields.
§  meme. Richard Dawkins’s term for a thought that can be spread through social networks.
§  meta level. A domain that is more abstract or derivative than some domain it depends on (the "object level"). A conversation can be said to operate on a meta level when it switches from discussing a set of simple or concrete objects to discussing higher-order or indirect features of those objects.
§  metaethics. A theory about what it means for ethical statements to be correct, or the study of such theories. Whereas applied ethics speaks to questions like "Is murder wrong?" and "How can we reduce the number of murders?", metaethics speaks to questions like "What does it mean for something to be wrong?" and "How can we generally distinguish right from wrong?"
§  Minimum Message Length Principle. A formalization of Occam’s Razor that judges the probability of a hypothesis based on how long it would take to communicate the hypothesis plus the available data. Simpler hypotheses are favored, as are hypotheses that can be used to concisely encode the data.
§  MIRI. See “Machine Intelligence Research Institute.”
§  money pump. A person who is irrationally willing to accept sequences of trades that add up to an expected loss.
§  motivated cognition. Reasoning and perception that is driven by some goal or emotion of the reasoner that is at odds with accuracy. Examples of this include non-evidence-based inclinations to reject a claim (motivated skepticism), to believe a claim (motivated credulity), to continue evaluating an issue (motivated continuation), or to stop evaluating an issue (motivated stopping).
§  mutual information. For two variables, the amount that knowing about one variable tells you about the other's value. If two variables have zero mutual information, then they are independent; knowing the value of one does nothing to reduce uncertainty about the other.
§  nanotechnology. Technologies based on the fine-grained control of matter on a scale of molecules, or smaller. If known physical law (or the machinery inside biological cells) is any guide, it should be possible in the future to design nanotechnological devices that are much faster and more powerful than any extant machine.
§  natural selection. The process by which heritable biological traits change in frequency due to their effect on how much their bearers reproduce.
§  negentropy. Negative entropy. A useful concept because it allows one to think of thermodynamic regularity as a limited resource one can possess and make use of, rather than as a mere absence of entropy.
§  Newcomb’s Problem. A central problem in decision theory. Imagine an agent that can predict your decisions in advance decides to either fill two boxes with money, or fill one box, based on their prediction. They put $1000 in a transparent box no matter what, and they then put $1 million in an opaque box if (and only if) they predicted that you’d only take the opaque box. The predictor tells you about this, and then leaves. Which do you pick? If you take both boxes, you get only the $1000, because the predictor foresaw your choice and didn’t fill the opaque box. On the other hand, if you only take the opaque box, you leave with $1 million. So it seems like you should take only the opaque box. However, many people object to this strategy on the grounds that you can’t causally control what the predictor did in the past; the predictor has already made their decision at the time when you make yours, and regardless of whether or not they placed the $1 million in the opaque box, you’ll be throwing away a free $1000 if you choose not to take it. This view that we should take both boxes is prescribed by causal decision theory, which (for much the same reason) prescribes defecting in Prisoner’s Dilemmas (even if you’re playing against a perfect atom-by-atom copy of yourself).
§  normality. (a) What’s commonplace. (b) What’s expected, prosaic, and unsurprising. Categorizing things as “normal” or weird” can cause one to conflate these two definitions, as though something must be inherently extraordinary or unusual just because one finds it surprising or difficult to predict. This is an example of confusing a feature of mental maps with a feature of the territory.
§  normativity. A generalization of morality to include other desirable behaviors and outcomes. If it would be prudent and healthy and generally a good idea for me to go jogging, then there is a sense in which I should go jogging, even if I’m not morally obliged to do so. Prescriptions about what one ought to do are normative, even when the kind of “ought” involved isn’t moral or interpersonal.
§  object level. A domain that is relatively concrete -- e.g. the topic of a conversation, or the target of an action. One might call one’s belief that murder is wrong "object-level" to contrast it with a meta-level belief about moral beliefs, or about the reason murder is wrong, or about something else that pertains to murder in a relatively abstract and indirect way.
§  objective. (a) Remaining real or true regardless of what one’s opinions or other mental states are. (b) Conforming to generally applicable moral or epistemic norms (e.g. fairness or truth) rather than to one’s biases or idiosyncrasies. (c) Perceived or acted on by an agent. (d) A goal.
§  Objectivism. A philosophy and social movement invented by Ayn Rand, known for promoting self-interest and laissez-faire capitalism as “rational.”
§  Occam’s Razor. The principle that, all else being equal, a simpler claim is more probable than a relatively complicated one. Formalizations of Occam’s Razor include Solomonoff induction and the Minimum Message Length Principle.
§  odds ratio. A way of representing how likely two events are relative to each other. For example, if I have no information about which day of the week it is, the odds are 1:6 that it’s Sunday. If x:y is the odds ratio, the probability of x is x / (x + y); so the prior probability that it’s Sunday is 1/7. Likewise, if P is my probability and I want to convert it into an odds ratio, I can just write P : (1 - P). For a percent probability, this becomes P : (100 - P). If my probability of winning a race is 40%, my odds are 40:60, which can also be written 2:3. Odds ratios are useful because they are easy to update. If I notice that the mall is closing early, and that’s twice as likely to happen on a Sunday as it is on a non-Sunday (a likelihood ratio of 2:1), I can simply multiply the left and right sides of my prior that it’s Sunday (1:6) by the evidence’s likelihood ratio (2:1) to arrive at a correct posterior probability of 2:6, or 1:3. This means that if I guess it’s Sunday, I should expect to be right 1/4 of the time -- 1 time for every 3 times I’m wrong. This is usually faster to calculate than Bayes’s Rule for real-numbered probabilities.
§  Omega. A hypothetical arbitrarily powerful agent used in various thought experiments.
§  ontology. An account of the things that exist, especially one that focuses on their most basic and general similarities. Things are “ontologically distinct” if they are of two fundamentally different kinds.
§  optimization process. Yudkowsky’s term for an agent or agent-like phenomenon that produces surprisingly specific (e.g. rare or complex) physical structures. A generalization of the idea of efficiency and effectiveness, or “intelligence.” The formation of water molecules and planets isn’t “surprisingly specific” in this context, because it follows in a relatively simple and direct way from garden-variety particle physics. For similar reasons, the existence of rivers does not seem to call for a particularly high-level or unusual explanation. On the other hand, the existence of trees seems too complicated for us to usefully explain it without appealing to an optimization process such as evolution. Likewise, the arrangement of wood into a well-designed dam seems too complicated to usefully explain without appealing to an optimization process such as a human, or a beaver.
§  Overcoming Bias. The blog where Yudkowsky originally wrote most of the content of Rationality: From AI to Zombies. It can be found at [www.overcomingbias.com], where it now functions as the personal blog of Yudkowsky’s co-blogger, Robin Hanson. Most of Yudkowsky’s writing is now hosted on the community blog Less Wrong.
§  pebble and bucket. An example of a system for mapping reality, analogous to memory or belief. One picks some variable in the world, and places pebbles in the bucket when the variable’s value (or one’s evidence for its value) changes. The point of this illustrative example is that the mechanism is very simple, yet achieves many of the same goals as properties that see heated philosophical debate, such as perception, truth, knowledge, meaning, and reference.
§  phase space. A mathematical representation of physical systems in which each axis of the space is a degree of freedom (a property of the system that must be specified independently) and each point is a possible state.
§  phlogiston. A substance hypothesized in the 17th century to explain phenomena such as fire and rust. Combustible objects were thought by late alchemists and early chemists to contain phlogiston, which evaporated during combustion.
§  photon. An elementary particle of light.
§  physicalism. The belief that all mental phenomena can in principle be reduced to physical phenomena. May also be referred to as “materialism”.
§  positive bias. Bias toward noticing what a theory predicts you’ll see instead of noticing what a theory predicts you won’t see.
§  possible world. A way the world could have been. One can say “there is a possible world in which Hitler won World War II” instead of “Hitler could have won World War II,” making it easier to contrast the features of multiple hypothetical or counterfactual scenarios. Not to be confused with the worlds of the many-worlds interpretation of quantum physics or Max Tegmark's Mathematical Universe Hypothesis, which are claimed (by their proponents) to be actual.
§  posterior probability. An agent’s beliefs after acquiring evidence. Contrasted with its prior beliefs, or priors.
§  prior probability. An agent’s information -- beliefs, expectations, etc. -- before acquiring some evidence. The agent’s beliefs after processing the evidence are its posterior probability.
§  Prisoner’s Dilemma. A game in which each player can choose to either "cooperate" or "defect" with the other. The best outcome for each player is to defect while the other cooperates, and the worst outcome is to cooperate while the other defects. Mutual cooperation is second-best, and mutual defection is second-worst. On conventional analyses, this means that defection is always the correct move: it improves your reward if the other player independently cooperates, and it lessens your loss if the other player independently defects. This leads to the pessimistic conclusion that many real-world conflicts that resemble Prisoner’s Dilemmas will inevitably end in mutual defection even though both players would be better off if they could find a way to force themselves to mutually cooperate. A minority of game theorists argue that mutual cooperation is possible even when the players cannot coordinate, provided that the players are both rational and both know that they are both rational. This is because two rational players in symmetric situations should pick the same option; so each player knows that the other player will cooperate if they cooperate, and will defect if they defect.
§  probability. A number representing how likely a statement is to be true. Bayesians favor using the mathematics of probability to describe and prescribe subjective states of belief, whereas frequentists generally favor restricting probability to objective frequencies of events.
§  probability theory. The branch of mathematics concerned with defining statistical truths and quantifying uncertainty.
§  problem of induction. In philosophy, the question of how we can justifiably assert that the future will resemble the past (scientific induction) without relying on evidence that presupposes that very fact.
§  proposition. Something that is either true or false. Commands, requests, questions, cheers, and excessively vague or ambiguous assertions are not propositions in this strict sense. Some philosophers identify propositions with sets of possible worlds. They think of propositions like “snow is white” not as particular patterns of ink in books, but rather as the thing held in common by all logically consistent scenarios featuring white snow. This is one way of abstracting away from how sentences are worded, what language they are in etc. and merely discussing what makes the sentences true or false.
§  quantum mechanics. The branch of physics that studies subatomic phenomena and their nonclassical implications for larger structures, and the mathematical formalisms used by physicists to predict such phenomena. Although the predictive value of such formalisms is extraordinarily well-established experimentally, physicists continue to debate how to incorporate gravitation into quantum mechanics, whether there are more fundamental patterns underlying quantum phenomena, and why the formalisms require a “Born rule” to relate the deterministic evolution of the wavefunction under Schrödinger’s equation to observed experimental outcomes. Related to the last question is a controversy in philosophy of physics over the physical significance of quantum-mechanical concepts like “wavefunction”, for instance whether this mathematical structure in some sense exists objectively, or whether it is merely a convenience for calculation.
§  quark. An elementary particle of matter.
§  rationalist. A person interested in rationality, especially one who is attempting to use new insights from psychology and the formal sciences to become more rational.
§  rationality. The property of employing useful cognitive procedures. Making systematically good decisions (instrumental rationality) based on systematically accurate beliefs (epistemic rationality).
§  recursion. A sequence of similar actions that each build on the result of the previous action.
§  reduction. An explanation of a phenomenon in terms of its origin or parts, especially one that allows you to re-describe the phenomenon without appeal to your previous conception of it.
§  reductionism. (a) The practice of scientifically reducing complex phenomena to simpler underpinnings. (b) The belief that such reductions are generally possible.
§  representativeness heuristic. A cognitive heuristic where one judges the probability of an event based on how well it matches some mental prototype or stereotype.
§  Schrödinger equation. A fairly simple partial differential equation that defines how quantum wavefunctions evolve over time. This equation is deterministic. It is not known why the Born Rule, which converts the wavefunction into an experimental prediction, is probabilistic; though there have been many attempts to make headway on that question.
§  scope insensitivity. A cognitive bias where large changes in an important value have little or no effect on one's behavior.
§  screening off. Making something informationally irrelevant. A piece of evidence A screens off a piece of evidence B from a hypothesis C if, once you know about A, learning about B doesn’t affect the probability of C.
§  search tree. A graph with a root node that branches into child nodes, which can then either terminate or branch once more. The tree data structure is used to locate values. In chess, for example, each node can represent a move, which branches into the other player’s possible responses, and searching the tree is intended to locate winning sequences of moves.
§  separate magisteria. See “magisterium.”
§  sequences. Yudkowsky’s name for short series of thematically linked blog posts or essays.
§  Singularity. One of several claims about a radical future increase in technological advancement. Kurzweil’s “accelerating change” singularity claims that there is a general, unavoidable tendency for technology to improve faster and faster. Vinge’s “event horizon” singularity claims that intelligences will develop that are too advanced for humans to model. Yudkowsky’s “intelligence explosion” singularity claims that self-improving AI will improve its own ability to self-improve, thereby rapidly achieving superintelligence. These claims are often confused with one another.
§  Solomonoff induction. An attempted definition of optimal (albeit computationally infeasible) reasoning. A combination of Bayesian updating with a simplicity prior that assigns less probability to percept-generating programs the longer they are.
§  subjective. (a) Conscious, experiential. (b) Dependent on the particular distinguishing features of agents, for example mental states. (c) Playing favorites, disregarding others’ knowledge or preferences, or otherwise violating some norm as a result of personal biases. Importantly, something can be subjective in sense (a) or (b) without being subjective in sense (c). For example, one’s ice cream preferences and childhood memories are “subjective” in a perfectly healthy sense.
§  superintelligence. An agent much smarter (more intellectually resourceful, rational, etc.) than present-day humans. This can be a purely hypothetical agent or it can be a predicted future technology.
§  System 1. The brain’s fast, automatic, emotional, and intuitive judgments.
§  System 2. The brain’s slow, deliberative, reflective, and intellectual judgments.
§  Taboo. A game by Hasbro where you try to get teammates to guess what word you have in mind while avoiding conventional ways of communicating it. Yudkowsky uses this as an analogy for the rationalist skill of linking words to the concrete evidence you use to decide when to apply them. Ideally, one should be know what one is saying well enough to paraphrase the message in several different ways, and to replace abstract generalizations with concrete observations.
§  terminal value. A goal that is pursued for its own sake, and not just to further some other goal.
§  territory. See “map and territory.”
§  theorem. A statement that has been mathematically or logically proven.
§  Traditional Rationality. Yudkowsky’s term for the scientific norms and conventions espoused by thinkers like Richard Feynman, Thomas Kuhn, Karl Popper, Carl Sagan, Martin Gardner, and Charles S. Peirce. Yudkowsky contrasts this with the ideas of rationality in contemporary mathematics and cognitive science.
§  truth-value. A proposition’s truth or falsity. True statements and false statements have truth-values, but questions, imperatives, and strings of gibberish do not. “Value” is meant here in a mathematical sense, not a moral one.
§  Unfriendly AI. A hypothetical smarter-than-human artificial intelligence that causes a global catastrophe by pursuing a goal without regard for humanity’s well-being. Yudkowsky predicts that superintelligent AI will be “Unfriendly” by default, unless a special effort goes into researching how to give AI stable, known, humane goals. Unfriendliness doesn’t imply malice, anger, or other human characteristics. A completely impersonal optimization process can be “Unfriendly” even if its only goal is to make paperclips. This is because even a goal as innocent as “maximize the expected number of paperclips” could motivate an AI to treat humans as competitors for physical resources, or as threats to the AI’s aspirations.
§  updating. Revising one’s beliefs in light of new evidence. If the updating is epistemically rational (i.e. it follows the follows the rules of probability theory) then it counts as Bayesian inference.
§  utilitarianism. An ethical theory asserting that one should act in a way that causes the most net benefit to people. Standard utilitarianism argues that acts can be justified even if they are morally counterintuitive and harmful, provided that the benefit outweighs the harm.
§  utility. The amount some outcome satisfies a set of goals, as defined by a utility function.
§  utility function. A function that ranks outcomes by how well they satisfy some set of goals.
§  utility maximizer. An agent that always picks actions with better outcomes over ones with worse outcomes (relative to its utility function). An expected utility maximizer is more realistic, given that real-world agents must deal with ignorance and uncertainty. It picks the actions that are likeliest to maximize its utility, given the available evidence. An expected utility maximizer’s decisions would sometimes be suboptimal in hindsight or from an omniscient perspective; but they won’t be foreseeably inferior to any alternative decision given the agent’s available evidence. Humans can sometimes be usefully modeled as expected utility maximizers with a consistent utility function, but this is at best an approximation, since humans are not perfectly rational.
§  utilon. Yudkowsky’s name for a unit of utility, i.e. something that satisfies a goal. The term is deliberately vague, to permit discussion of desired and desirable things without relying on imperfect proxies such as monetary value and self-reported happiness.
§  wavefunction. A complex-valued function used in quantum mechanics to explain and predict the wave-like behavior of physical systems at small scales. Realists about the wavefunction treat it as a good characterization of the way the world really is, more fundamental than earlier atomic models. Anti-realists disagree, although they grant that the wavefunction is a useful tool by virtue of its mathematical relationship to observed properties of particles (the Born Rule).
§  winning. Yudkowsky’s term for getting what you want. The result of instrumental rationality.
§  zombie. In philosophy, a perfect atom-by-atom replica of a human that lacks a human’s subjective awareness. Zombies behave exactly like humans, but they lack consciousness. Some philosophers argue that the idea of zombies is coherent -- that zombies, although not real, are at least logically possible. They conclude from this that facts about first-person consciousness are logically independent of physical facts, and that our world breaks down into both physical and nonphysical components. Most philosophers reject the idea that zombies are logically possible, though the topic continues to be actively debated.





Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Don't accept a Nobel Prize -- and other tips for improving your rationality